Kick The Cops Off Your Block

116214605_312357293297712_3481169293133589828_n

07/31/20

Abolish the Police: 

Our communities are occupied by the cops. They put our friends, loved ones, and neighbors in prison, they consistently use unjust violence, they enforce property at the expense of human freedom and life, they criminalize dissent against the state, and they disproportionately target the working class, the dispossessed, Black people, Brown people, Indigenous people, trans people, and disabled people. Cops are defined by a double standard of violence. The very political, economic, and social inequality and unjust laws that cops are defined by enforcing–regardless of the intention of any individual cop– are the biggest causes we know of for overall violence in society (Link to statistics and analysis at end of pamphlet).

As of 2020, The USA has the most prisoners per capita in the world and has less than 5% of the world’s population and over 20% of the world’s prison population. One in three Black men born before 2001 will go to prison in their lifetime, and Black women are over 5 times as likely to go to prison as white women. 76% of people who go to prison are arrested again within 5 years, the highest repeat offense rate in the world. There has been a 700% increase in women incarcerated since 1980. (Links to statistics are at the end of this pamphlet). Although cops in the USA are particularly egregious, there are fundamental problems with any kind of cops.

Cops by definition necessarily enforce hierarchical laws and political economic class relations. Such hierarchical laws and class relations are unjust because they increase overall violence in society, decrease overall happiness in society, and do not allow individuals and collectives to make decisions proportionate to how they are affected by decisions. Therefore the position of cop is unjust, because cops by definition necessarily enforce unjust laws and unjust relations. Given cops enforce hierarchies, and that many of such hierarchies require cops (and other kinds of enforcement), we need to do more than just abolish cops; we also need to abolish hierarchical institutions and relations. Additionally, we need to find ways to meet our needs and organize with each other politically, economically, and socially without rulers.

Alternatives to the police:

Most of what the cops do is enforce inequality and unjust laws (such as victimless crimes like drug possession, enforcement of property over human freedom, and unjust ways of solving real problems that exacerbate overall injustice). We do need conflict resolution, and ways to interdependently support one another, but we do not need the cops to manage that for us. Instead we can handle conflict resolution through talking with each other directly–or in a way that is mediated by an agreed upon facilitator (or conflict resolution council)– to work through a conflict and decide how to resolve it. Transformative and restorative justice processes reduce recidivism and have a higher victim satisfaction rate than punitive justice. Additionally, we can use self defense against people who are unjustly using violence against us or others– distinct from punishment.  We can train each other in self defense so that self defense isn’t monopolized. We can organize collective self defense without hierarchical structure and without arbitrary rule. People should also learn and teach each other about an ethics of justified self  defense so that it is used in a way that advances freedom and equality while minimizing overall violence. People can call their friends, neighbors, and community assembly communication networks in times of emergency conflicts. Non-violent unarmed third party mediation teams can be on call. And additionally, we can abolish authoritarian relations that are the biggest causes of unjust violence towards people.

From here to there: 

Do you have three to five friends in a given area that have similar politics in favor of abolishing the police and providing mutual support to one another to meet each other’s needs? Then you can get together with other people in your block or neighborhood to start working on mutual aid projects and police abolition. Community assemblies can help to address the ways that cops–and the politicians who unleash them and the business as usual that cops protect– are harming people. Community assemblies can pool needs, abilities, tools, resources, and ideas together to help people and groups mutually support one another. In and beyond community assemblies, people can make decisions together about how to go about abolishing the police, how to build community, how to create infrastructure to meet each other’s needs (and the needs of others), how to take action against unjust inequality and unjust limits to freedom etc.

This can look like organizing or co-organizing protests, supporting uprisings with mutual aid networks, hosting skill shares and public education events, forming community copwatch groups, forming community tenants’ unions, providing tools and resources to each other, assisting direct actions, free food distribution for people, and teaming up with other neighborhoods and groups and individuals to make entire sections of the city a cop free zone. By supporting each other within and across collectives and communities, we can make every block ungovernable by the state while providing non-hierarchical solutions to social problems. It is important for people-powered organizations to generalize in society along with direct actions and mutual aid so that long term idealistic goals can be practically arrived at through dialogue, coordination, and collective decisions before, during, and after uprisings and revolutions.

Community assemblies can make decisions together through direct democracy, free association and non-hierarchy. Together, these principles foster collective decisions, free participation and dissent by individuals, and an assembly with a form and content that does not create or support any ruling class or strata over and above people. These cellular block by block community assemblies can link up in networks of mutual support with other neighborhoods, communities, and collectives. Mutual aid infrastructure can assist any direct action effort– as every direct action effort has a sphere of social reproduction. Whether its an occupation, a blockade, a picket, or an insurrection, mutual aid organizations, networks and infrastructure can help literally fuel the needs of participants increasing the overall capacity of people powered organizations and actions allowing them to sustain overtime while reaching out to people and helping people at the same time.

Organizing community assemblies can be done through a potluck, then a meeting, followed by an informal gathering. Some meetings can be specifically issue oriented– such as mutual aid based or rooted in abolishing the police (or some other kind of oppositional politics and direct action). This can help keep give them a common goal and political focus. The assembly can overtime branch into a plurality of issues. People can then get to know each other, form friendships, talk politics, and find shared action projects to do together– within and beyond the assembly project. Overtime, assemblies can develop mutual aid collectives and infrastructure, create direct action networks and help with direct actions (such as occupations, pickets, blocking infrastructure, and assisting strikes), develop conflict resolution infrastructure (rooted in transformative and restorative justice as opposed to judges, police, and prisons), and find ways to strategically oppose the police and assist movements against the police in their neighborhoods and beyond.

People can promote community assemblies through door knocking, flyering, handbills, an online presence of some kind, and connecting with like-minded groups as well as with individuals one on one. These assemblies can build on already existing community ties and bring them into solidarity for a world where people make direct decisions about what affects them without bosses, politicians, cops, or oppression. Community assemblies have the potential to unite the widest array of people along common liberatory practice and are required for self-management to exist on every scale. If people are not making decisions about what affects them directly then decision making power is de facto privatized. Direct decision making should exist on a community scale in a way that does not arbitrarily limit the individual freedoms that we should have. This is not just about strategy, but what it means to live in a good society.

Process for meetings can be as simple as making an agenda, having a temporary facilitator who calls on people as they raise their hands, having a discussion, proposing decisions and alternatives, and then making collective decisions through dialogue. Assemblies and collectives can form committees and have delegates to implement specific decisions. Committees and delegates of assemblies and collectives should not make any decisions over and above the groups they are delegated by– instead they should carry out decisions they agree to do that are made by people directly.

Community assemblies are not the only kinds of organizations one can create for a better world; for example, there is the affinity group form which allows a small group of people to work together on specific actions. This can make sense for stuff that is intended to be underground, but also has other functions. Additionally people can form medic collectives, gardening collectives, mutual-aid collectives, bail-fund collectives, direct action collectives, community defense collectives, childcare collectives, community or worker controlled cooperatives, land trusts, radical unions, etc.  All of these different forms should use some kind of direct democracy (direct collective decision making) internally for ethical reasons and strategic reasons; cooperative conflict between people working on common goals allows better decisions and allows everyone to participate, agree, disagree, amend, question, critique, dissent, etc.

Different and similar kinds of groups can link up together for mutual aid, common projects, and joint actions. When working together, each group can communicate through direct written communication from groups and meetings of delegates from each group. This should be done in a way where collective decisions are made between groups but where all decision making power resides directly within each group’s membership–where delegates are communicative rather than representative policy makers. This can build towards something like a police abolition coalition that is in favor of defunding and abolishing the police and in favor of mutual aid and transformative justice. This kind of coalition can exist within and between regions. Such a coalition can catalyze and create momentum for police abolition, fuel liberatory social movements with capacity, can develop people powered infrastructure for meeting needs and resolving conflicts, and can win concessions from the state that minimize the police, while building towards revolution. Of course, we need to do more than just win concessions and we need to do more than just abolishing the local police; we also need to abolish sheriffs, state police, federal police, private police, and be prepared to oppose right wing militias who try to fill the void of the police. In order to abolish the police we must abolish the class relations which necessitate a police force ruling over and above people. In order to make sure that hierarchy does not emerge, we are going to need to develop horizontalist democratic processes for decision making as well as egalitarian cultural dimensions that can abolish and replace white supremacy, patriarchy, and other forms of oppression.

We need a diversity of tactics and a diversity of organizations to fill different niches. If we want to kick the cops off our block, we must strategically work within our given contexts as they develop and find out how to make decisions together without resorting to rulers and without arbitrarily limiting the freedoms people should have.

More Info: 

Statistics Sources: 

https://www.sentencingproject.org/issues/racial-disparity/

Transformative Justice: 

Organizing 101:

https://thenewmunicipalagenda.wordpress.com/2020/02/03/libertarian-socialist-method/

https://libcom.org/organise/general/articles/decision-making-and-organisational-form.php

Poverty and Inequality increases rates of violence:

https://www.equalitytrust.org.uk/violence

Direct Action 101 Guide:

https://archive.org/details/DirectActionSurvivalGuide_210

Mutual Aid 101:

Mutual Aid

https://mutualaiddisasterrelief.org/mutual-aid/embed/#?secret=VPAFsWUDHL

Communalism 101:

https://thenewmunicipalagenda.wordpress.com/2017/09/19/introduction-to-neighborhood-assemblies/

https://www.communalismpamphlet.net/

https://libcom.org/library/mountain-river-has-many-bends

Origins of Police: 

https://libcom.org/history/origins-police-david-whitehouse

Community Self Defense Manual:

https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Let-Your-Motto-Be-Resistance%3A-A-Handbook-on-New-and-Movement/44879ede18e7176efa0d9aff3601fdf44c13fcb0

Libertarian Socialist Method

better rose

02/03/20

Libertarian Socialist Method:

  1. Minimum common terms of practice include direct democracy, non-hierarchy, co-federalism, respecting what should be guaranteed collective and individual freedoms (including but not limited to a substantial free association).*glossary definitions provided below.
  2. Such universal principles are then adapted to specific contexts and relevant conditions.
  3. People make decisions about what affects them–including political economic life– in egalitarian and participatory ways through deliberation and direct decision making processes.
  4. In deliberation processes, people can express proposals, needs, what people are able and willing to do to meet general needs, concerns, critiques, dissent, amendments, inquiries, other possibilities, preferences, scientific information, technical information, philosophical information, etc. and try to use collective wisdom to round out proposals to arrive at collective decisions.
  5. Such a process should happen within and between collectives on a variety of scales. For implementation of decisions, embedded participatory councils of assemblies and embedded rotating delegates of assemblies can be mandated and immediately recallable by general assemblies and given no policy making power. Implementation of collective decisions made at general assemblies is self managed within the bounds of the policy made at general assemblies.
  6. The right kind of freedom and the right kind of equality are goals to be approached and embodied within the process of organizations. The content of such a process should use oppositional politics against that which should not exist and reconstructive politics to create that which should exist, to meet people’s needs, create a realm of egalitarian freedom, and to treat ecological systems with rational care.
  7. Process continues onwards for reevaluation and new content.

The content that fills this process needs to be created by people interfacing with libertarian socialist processes. The form and process of libertarian socialist practice are not sufficient to arrive at such goals and content by themselves. Persons and collectives must fill it with a good and strategic content to arrive at various goals. Such a process–form and content wise– should be adapted specific contexts (while keeping its necessary features) to arrive at revolutions where such libertarian socialist processes become political economic decision making processes. However, doing so is notoriously difficult for there are many relevant variables about specific localities one is in with all of their specific social relationships which are themselves changing. That being said, there are some general patterns and lessons we can discern for how we should move forward, build a movement worth developing, and fight for a world worth fighting for. We should always go back and forth between our process and our content refining each to be ethically principled and refining each to be conducive to various goals worth striving towards.

Glossary Definitions:

  1. Direct Democracy: Direct collective decision making processes.
  2. Non-Hierarchy: The absence of institutionalized ruling classes, strata, and top-down command-obedience relations.
  3. Co-Federalism: Organizing together across collectives in such a way where persons and collectives retain their freedom to make decisions directly while making decisions on a plurality of scales from the bottom upwards from the local, to regional, and inter-regional scales.
  4. Substantial Free Association: Includes Freedom of association, freedom from association, and freedom within associations. Freedom within associations can only be arrived at through horizontalism and participatory relations that lack arbitrary coercion and discrimination.

Sortition and Volition

Lottery balls

 

What is about to be stated is by no means universal but: More leftist organizations should use sortition and volition to implement decisions more of the time than they do. Sortition and volition can take a plurality of different forms. One such way for sortition and volition to work is to have it so people get chosen by lot–for example out of a hat– to implement various policies and roles for a set period of time before they are rotated. People chosen by lot would then be able to agree or disagree to do the specific role. Delegates chosen through sortition would be accountable to and recallable by general assemblies. All of the policy making power would be at the level of the general assemblies directly. Another way to do the sorition process would be to make it so all the people being put into the “randomized” process would agree to a plurality of roles prior to being chosen for any specific role. Examples of roles could be: sending out emails, facilitating meetings, being a delegate to communicate between assemblies or organizations, doing door-to-door work, etc. 

 

 Such a process of sortition and volition is good because 1. It helps break down racialized and gendered divisions of labor. 2. it gives people opportunities to learn new skills (the roles can be staggered to teach such skills and to be back up in case someone doesn’t do what they are responsible for) which can break down other divisions of labor. 3. It makes it so people who are putting in too much get some slack 4. it makes it so people who are putting in too much relinquish such roles to others (this is good for overall egalitarianism and spreading of informal and implementation power and responsibilities) 5. It makes it so people who are not putting in enough are encouraged to chip in and are given a way to do so (which they might not get in a delegation process). Various roles can be staggered to teach skills to others while acting as a contingency in case people do not follow through.

Towards Communalist Especifism

Doc5tLPXUAEQG6E

11/09/19

Communalism:

Communalism is rooted in the development of horizontalist democratic community assemblies. Communalism is a “revolutionary political theory and practice, deeply rooted in the general socialist tradition” that would not just seek to create cooperative relations but forms that “confront capital and the basic structures of state power” (5). Communalist assemblies have bylaws, bills of rights, and structures that embody terms of practice rooted in libertarian socialist principles. Such principles include but are not limited to Non-hierarchy, Direct Democracy, Co-federation, and Ecology. Community assemblies–and co-federations thereof– make policies that can be implemented by participatory committees and delegates that are mandated by community assemblies and immediately recallable by community assemblies. Embedded committees and delegates within horizontalist community assemblies do not have policy making power over and above community assemblies (1). Communalist assemblies have decision making processes rooted in deliberation, and cooperative conflict, and direct democracy to come to collective decisions–while respecting what should be the rights of persons and collectives. Communalist assemblies would additionally aim towards needs based distribution. Such community assemblies could create embedded committees and auxiliary collectives, while also planning direct actions and mutual aid projects, while additionally helping with popular education. Communalist assemblies–and co-federations thereof– would link up together to do both oppositional and reconstructive politics at the points of extraction, production, reproduction, distribution, and at the point of the community sphere. Communalist assemblies would also prefigure such assemblies as forms of governance to exist in a post revolutionary society–rather than merely forms to bring about a revolution or merely forms for after the revolution.

Especifism and Communalism:

Communalism and especifism are both libertarian communist tendencies. They share an ethical, organizational, and strategic orientation in regards to direct democracy, anti-hierarchy, federalism, distribution according to needs, and revolutionary politics. The focus both tendencies have on libertarian governance (rather than no governance) prior to, during, and after revolutions place both tendencies firmly in the organizational branch of anti-state socialism. Despite encompassing a majority of anarchism’s history–and the majority of anarchism’s victories– the most organizational branches of anti state socialism are not considered anarchism proper by a significant number of anarchists and non-anarchists alike.

Especifist praxis is rooted in, “1. The need for specifically anarchist organization built around a unity of ideas and praxis. 2. The use of the specifically anarchist organization to theorize and develop strategic political and organizing work 3. Active involvement in and building of autonomous and popular social movements, which is described as the process of “social insertion.” (3). The specific ideological agreements especifist groups have include libertarian socialist/communist principles as well as some dimensions that platformists share such as theoretical unity, tactical unity, federalism and collective responsibility. However, that agreement with platformism does not mean complete agreement to everything written in the original platform– which was written in regards to a very specific revolutionary context involving military action (4). Furthermore, especifism has made advances compared to traditional platformism in regards to its theory of what the relationship between ideologically libertarian socialists specific groups and broader social movements should be– in part by going way beyond relationships of ideologically specific libertarian socialist groups to labor unions into a broader conception of organizations and social movements against hierarchy (3). This makes especifist groups well suited to have strategic relationships to community assemblies and daily struggles in and out of the workplace. Such a relationship of especifist groups to community assemblies is something that has already developed in practice by especifists (3). Furthermore, especifism is in favor of a strategic unity to get from here to a libertarian socialist revolution based on common analysis, shared theory and social insertion rather than mere tactical unity (3).

Social insertion has a very advanced and practical understanding of the relationships between ideologically specific organizations and social movements. Especifists center their strategy of social change around a mutualistic relationship between ideologically specific libertarian communist groups and a broader social movement. As the Black Rose Federation article “Building a Revolutionary Anarchism” (2) describes and prescribes: There should be dual membership within ideologically specific libertarian socialist organizations and within popular organizations. Doing so puts libertarian socialists in contact with broader populations than merely themselves. Within such movements, libertarian socialists should advocate for practices of horizontalist democracy, direct action, anti capitalism, and class struggle to further the goals of social movements–as well as argue for such positions when they are minority positions as active minorities furthering libertarian socialist practice. Especifist groups are in favor of popularizing libertarian socialist practice in large part teaching by demonstration. Such a process can help make libertarian socialism relevant to the lives of people struggling towards liberatory goals of various kinds in class struggle and daily struggle in and out of the workplace. Such a process can combine revolutionary organizing with popular organizing. Especifist groups and libertarian socialists–and various groups centered around such theory and/or practice– should help social movements by enabling them to access their greatest strength: the capacity of thousands of people thinking and acting together (which can be better unleashed through direct democracy). Hierarchical organizations inhibit participation from people involved, whereas directly democratic organizing can give people more ways to participate meaningfully. Without a class struggle perspective, social movements wind up making the wrong alliances and not engaging in the kinds of oppositional actions that are needed for revolution–defanging the social movements and disempowering membership. Libertarian socialists need social movements to ground libertarian socialism in popular movements and among the working class, the dispossessed, and oppressed more broadly, to learn organizational skills, to develop better praxis, and to minimize the disconnect between libertarian socialism and the general public. When doing so, it is important to not unnecessarily go against the tide– libertarian socialists should find the already existing common values and practices within popular organizations and social movements and then work to develop that already existing libertarian socialist and anti-hierarchical thrust (3). Furthermore, the goal of social insertion is to unite people in the social movement along such libertarian socialist practice– not necessarily getting any specific person to proclaim any specific ideology– although such social insertion would spread theory as well through dialogue. Specific popular education collectives can help supplement especifist groups, communalist assemblies, and broader social movements in spreading good praxis, in part through popularizing good theory through critical deliberation.

Communalist assemblies (rather than mere community assemblies) are popular assemblies in the community sphere that also have a coherent form and content– that at least follows from minimal libertarian socialist principles in conjunction with a community sphere and communal self-governance. Communalist assemblies are distinct from other kinds of popular organizations that primarily organize around specific workplace struggles and at the point of production such as syndicalist approaches. Communalist assemblies are also distinct from ideologically specific groups. Communalist assemblies do not require a shared ideology between individuals even though they necessarily have to have a shared terms of practice between people (which can be expressed in bylaws, bills of rights, structures, short term and long term programs of groups, or even points of unity for practice, etc.). Such practices are of course theory laden, and can be evaluated by theory. Furthermore the overall content of such processes are given a better lived content by the popularization of good theories, propositional knowledge, and practical knowledge. Communalist assemblies are designed to be much more inclusive compared to especifist groups–although especifist groups should seek popularity within the terms that make them ethical and effective without sacrificing their coherence and function to a false unity. Through having a coherent theoretical and strategic unity, especifist groups have a distinct function of spreading a specific praxis within social movements by helping to assist and develop coherent popular organizations, by advocating for libertarian socialist practices such as direct democracy and direct action to further more immediate goals of social movements and develop their liberatory dimensions, while also aiming towards long term vision of libertarian communism.

Communalists want community assemblies as revolutionary forms and also want the economy to be politicized– that is for the means of production, including land in use, to be put into the hands of co-federated communal assemblies that have embedded participatory councils that implement decisions within the mandate made from below (where all policy making power resides). Especifists are often, but by no means always, working with or in favor of communal forms of freedom that are either identical to or similar to the ones advocated for and practiced by communalists. Especifist groups have been more pluralistic than communalists in regards to the forms of economy and keystone revolutionary forms that they advocate. Often times especifist groups organize with and/or favor syndicalist formations and workers’ councils– but other times they might organize with and/or favor commune formations (and sometimes especifist groups will work with both or neither). Although working with such popular organizations of various kinds–communal assemblies, sydincalist unions, and workers’ councils, issue specific movements and organizations– can make sense towards developing a revolution, a modest appeal for communalism would be that the communalist political economy should be developed overtime because 1. Without a communalist political economy power is privatized over and above direct communities into segmented fields that make decisions over and above people affected by such economic matters 2. Self management within egalitarian bounds should be in every sphere including the communal sphere which necessitates a co-federated communal economy 3. That our means should be consistent with or conducive to such development. 4. Additionally, on a strategic level, communalism can organize oppositional and reconstructive politics at point of extraction, production, distribution, reproduction, and community life.

Towards Communalist Especifism:

Especifism is in favor of interfacing with popular organizations and social movements in a productive way as illustrated in the above section. A communalist especifist group would also be in favor of that approach while viewing communalist assemblies as keystone organizations to be developed alongside a plurality of other organizations. Such communalist assemblies would be keystone organizations for both ethical and strategic reasons: an ethical reason being that developing communalist assemblies is necessary for egalitarian self management in every sphere, and some strategic reasons for such an approach are that such assemblies are radically flexible to working on oppositional and reconstructive politics in every sphere, are able to be especially mutualistic towards other liberatory collectives and projects, and that such assemblies can prefigure such ethical ends through ethical consistency of means and ends in conjunction with strategic content.

Communalist assemblies could help broader social movements in regards to specific issues and struggles with both solidarity actions and capacity while in turn gaining support from social movements on future common actions. Expanding capacity of communalist assemblies would fuel projects of communalist assemblies as well as other liberatory social movements communalist assemblies become in solidarity with. Although it will usually make sense for communalist especifists to be developing developing community assembly projects, depending on the context they are in, it might make sense for communalist especifists to organize with other kinds of liberatory social movements to advocate for practices of direct action, direct democracy, opposition to hierarchy, and class struggle. That would help with maximizing overall participation and capacity of people involved in movements–and help qualify such participation through good terms of practice– to further the liberatory goals of social movements as well as the goal of developing libertarian socialism. In the process of struggle, it might make sense to add support to various groups and movements with solidarity from community assemblies if the exist, if such help is wanted, and if community assemblies are willing to help. It might even make sense to start community assemblies in the process of achieving some specific goal as part of some issue specific social movement.

Communalist especifists would advocate for and develop community assemblies as parts of social movements, and also advocate for and develop direct action, direct democracy, class struggle, and opposition to hierarchy within other social movements. This would generalize good praxis and strengthen the practice of broader social movements through advocating for interfacing with an ecosystem of groups (including communalist assemblies as well as a plurality of other bottom up organizations) when it strategically makes sense for the goals of specific struggles and goals. The communalist assemblies would be popular anti-state political organizations rooted in libertarian socialist practice on a community scale and the communalist especifst groups would be ideologically specific and tight knit advancing libertarian socialist practice and communalist practice within social movements through social insertion– mainly working with community assemblies but also on other fronts as it makes sense according to context. Ideologically specific communalist especifist groups would be in large part instrumentalized to establishing, catalyzing, and helping communalist assemblies and other bottom up projects become self managed and strategic.

There is a distinction between community assemblies and communalist assemblies. Whereas a community assembly is merely an assembly on a community sphere, a communalist assembly has additional qualifiers on top of being an assembly on the community scale. Communalist assemblies have a structure and strategic orientation that is qualified by libertarian socialist practice. Communalist especifists would in large part help community assemblies flourish into communalist assemblies through social insertion.

Especifists sometimes call the level of ideologically specific organization that they are involved with political and they often call popular movements social movements (4). This is distinct from the way communalists would use the term political. For communalists, politics refers to city management– and libertarian socialist politics would entail egalitarian participatory forms of community governance. Politics can be contrasted to statecraft through the state necessarily being hierarchical and politics potentially being non-hierarchical. There is nothing in city management itself that necessitates a ruling class. In this sense, communalist organizations are anti statist forms of political organizations (that have some specific qualifiers for them to be communalist assemblies and not merely community assemblies) that can be a part of and in relation to yet distinguished from mere social movements without adjectives. Social movements can include a plurality of organizations from communalist assemblies, to workers’ councils, to affinity groups, to direct action collectives and networks, mutual aid collectives and networks, popular education collectives, etc. Communalist especifists groups would practice development of social insertion within social movements more broadly, and also practice social insertion within community assemblies more specifically. Using the communalist categorization of politics, Especifism is of course political, as in related to politics, but so are social movements. An alternative categorical framing for Especifist groups is to say that they operate on an ideologically specific political level which is not equivalent to a political level more broadly as in relationship to city management–or the political level more specifically as a potentially non-hierarchical public sphere for communal deliberation and decisions about city management.

Endnotes:

  1. http://social-ecology.org/wp/2002/09/harbinger-vol-3-no-1-the-communalist-project/
  2. http://blackrosefed.org/building-a-revolutionary-anarchism/
  3. http://blackrosefed.org/especifismo-weaver/
  4. http://anarkismo.net/article/22146
  5. https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-toward-a-communalist-approach
  6. https://libcom.org/library/social-anarchism-organisation

Towards a Libertarian Socialist Bill of Rights

libertarian law

10/23/19

Ideological points of unity organizations–of various degrees of tightness and looseness– have specific niches that they fill in revolutionary processes. However, when organizing the unorganized and reaching people more broadly, they will not all share a libertarian socialist politics. Every group organizing together defacto has shared agreements. Making them explicit can allow people and the principles to be held accountable. However, enshrining such principles in an ideological points of unity statement–which is distinct from a points of unity statement that is merely for practices of a group– will alienate people who do not already agree with libertarian socialist politics. And having a popular organization without explicit shared processes and practices that are liberatory can either lead to hierarchical organizing or extreme incoherence. A way to keep many of the practical dimensions of such a points of unity enshrined within a popular organization–and to have such principles explicit while being distinct from a shared ideology–  is to have the principles woven into another defacto ‘point of unity’ of organizations– that is the constitutions and bylaws themselves which can be amended with a bill of rights. Within such constitutions and bylaws, decision making processes and positive and negative freedoms can be spelled out for persons and collectives. Although there is nothing about bylaws and bills of rights that are necessarily radical, they can function in libertarian socialist ways. When the practices of a good points of unity–for example direct democracy, non-hierarchy, ecology, and co-federalism– are enshrined in the constitution, bylaws and/or bill of rights, then the terms of engagement within an organization can be libertarian socialist (form and content wise to the degree that such libertarian socialist terms of practice are actually being practiced and developed). This can enable people from many ideological backgrounds to engage one another in a more ‘ideologically neutral’ and pluralistic space that nonetheless has agreement from people to work on specific terms of practice that are consistent with libertarian socialist freedoms and principles.

Ideological points of unity groups can have specific functions such as organizing with people who are in favor of a specific theoretical worldviews to spread a specific theory and practice within social movements, popular organizations, and the population more broadly. But that is a distinct function from a popular organization that is trying to organize as many people as possible through specific processes towards specific ends through deliberation, direct collective decision making, and direct action.

The forms of freedom are of course never sufficient for their own development and good content: It is possible to organize via forms of freedom to merely do merely benign activities– or worse, activities that are counterproductive and unstrategic according to ethical ends good (and libertarian socialist) criteria. It is up to the people involved in such organizations to fill those forms with liberatory and strategic content and the form is never sufficient to do that. However, to the degree a specific kind of form develops and reproduces itself, specific processes and necessarily features will follow. Liberatory forms are constitutive of the overall development of liberatory content and are an essential part of developing oppositional and reconstructive politics in harmony with, and conducive to, the flourishing of good ethical criteria.

An organization that has libertarian socialist structure, a libertarian socialist constitution and bill of rights, and libertarian socialist bylaws without an ideological points of unity document is consistent with the kind of political economic structures that ought to exist in a good society. In a good society, it is not like everyone will have to agree with x, y, and z ideology (in fact differentiation, cooperative conflict and dialogue are crucial towards any kind liberatory society) –however the better people’s theories are, the better the overall content of such political economic social development will generally be. “A communalist polity requires a written constitution and, yes, regulatory laws, to avoid a structurelessness that would yield mindless anarchy. The more defined the rights and duties of citizens are, the more easily can they be upheld as part of the general interest against the intrusion of petty tyrannies,” (Bookchin). What people and collectives will have to do in a good society is to organize with one another and interact with one another within certain minimal dimensions of what ought to be and ought to be permissible. This focus on shared minimal freedoms and duties for practices within a group–towards itself and others– is distinct from the ideological unity of ideologically specific libertarian socialist organizations.

It is good to have both kinds of organizations– ideologically specific libertarian socialist organizations, and popular organizations that enshrine libertarian socialist principles in the constitutions and bylaws (or even points of unity for practice) without being an ideologically specific group. An ideologically specific group can help start popular organizations with libertarian socialist bylaws, structures, and terms of practice. Furthermore, such ideologically specific libertarian socialist groups can advocate for libertarian socialist terms of practice within popular organizations and social movements to further the goals of such popular organizations and movements. 

The following is going to be a very crude jotting down of specific points that can be included in bylaws and bills of rights–after they have been critiqued, fleshed out, amended, and tweaked. The following jumbles various dimensions of bylaws with a bill of rights for those bylaws. Furthermore, it jumbles together different sections of the bylaws even further– for example there should be a decision making process section, a committee section, and a delegate section etc. The following is a crude example of how a libertarian socialist principles can be translated into a bill of rights from the principles Direct Democracy, Non-hierarchy, and co-federalism. Some of these points try to flesh out what ought to be a right in good society–as in they are aspirational rights to be developed that are there to qualify the content of decisions and to focus an assembly towards specific goals. 

This should be amended, critiqued, and fleshed out with some terms defined, and other terms swapped out for the definitions: 

  1. Communities, collectives, and persons should be able to make participatory self governed decisions within egalitarian boundaries bounded by the freedoms of others.  
  2. Communities, collectives, and persons should be free from hierarchical rule (institutionalized top-down command and obedience). 
  3. Communities, collectives, and persons should be free from arbitrary limits to freedoms (including but not limited to arbitrary discrimination).
  4. People should have the right to the means of existence. Food, water, shelter, energy, transportation, education, healthcare and everything people need in order to live–including the means of production– should be available to everyone for free.  
  5. Means of production (which includes instruments of production and land in use) should be held in common. Communities should have the right to self manage economic life through communal assemblies. Embedded participatory collectives can be created by communal assemblies for implementation of economic activity–assisted by technics– but policy making power for economics should be within community assemblies. Embedded collectives of communal assemblies self manage within the bounds of the policy created at the general assemblies.
  6. People should have the right to the means of politics. Everyone within a given locale–including transient people, immigrants, etc.– should be able to participate within political processes. *. prefigurative popular organizations prior to a revolution can of course exclude threats to assembly such as hierarchs, cops, and fascists. 
  7. Decision making process within general assemblies and committees: All decisions must be consistent with constitutions, bylaws and bills of rights. Decisions are to be made through deliberation via stack. Simple majority can mandate and recall deliberative processes such as a. rotation in a circle, b. Rotation of “in favor of” speaking and then “opposed to” speaking, c. Discussion between a few people speaking at length, d. unmoderated discussion, e. Straw polls f. Magnitude of agreement disagreement temperature checks, etc. Decision making aims towards consensus. Decisions are to be made by a threshold of Simple Majority when there is not consensus. Simple majority can mandate and recall other thresholds above 50%
  8. General assemblies can create committees. All committees of general assemblies are to be mandated and immediately recallable by general assemblies. Committees can make decisions within their mandates in regards to implementation. Committees can be made open or closed to specifically delegated people. Committees do not have the right to have policy making power over and above general assemblies from which they are mandated. Committees are to be participatory. Committee members will join through either sortition and volition, nomination and election, or whoever volunteers (for open committees). 
  9. General assemblies can have delegates for various purposes. All delegates of general assemblies are to be mandated by general assemblies and immediately recallable by general assemblies. Additionally delegate positions should be rotated. Delegates will either be delegated through nomination and election or through sortition and volition. Delegate roles should be staggered when needed–such as for new people in a specific delegate role. All delegates are to be administrative and coordinative. No delegates are to have policy making power over and above the general assembly that delegated them.   
  10. Communities, collectives, and persons should be able to freely federate together. All policy making power should remain in the hands of communities and collectives directly. 

I would like to end this article with a quote to reflect on. Freedoms are contingent upon our social responsibility towards them. As Bookchin said, “one of the great maxims of the First International, to which all factions subscribed, was Marx’s slogan: “No Rights Without Duties, No Duties Without Rights.” In a free society, as revolutionaries of all kinds generally understood, we would enjoy freedoms (“rights”), but we would also have responsibilities (“duties”) we would have to exercise. The concept of individual autonomy becomes meaningless when it denies the obligations that every individual owes to society as social responsibilities”.

https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/murray-bookchin-toward-a-communalist-approach

Here is Rojava’s social contract. It is an example of transforming libertarian socialist principles into a governing document for millions of people:

Social Contract of the Democratic Federation of Northern Syria

A Communalist Assembly Starter Kit

Painting-assembly-participants

12/15/18

How to Start a Communalist Assembly:

Communalism:

Communalism refers to the means and ends of directly democratic, non hierarchical, ecological, co-federated community assemblies that seek to meet people’s needs, decentralize power, oppose hierarchies, and to build the new world within the shell of the old via libertarian socialist dual power. It is a praxis–an intertwined theory and a practice– that applies universalist principles to particular contexts adapting to relevant conditions and variables accordingly. Communalist assemblies seek to intertwine reconstructive politics, oppositional politics, collective building, principled action, and consequential efficacy–ideally using an ethically principled process strategically to develop goals worth developing.

Forms of Freedom:

Communalist assemblies are rooted in specific practices that qualify the forms and contents of their decisions. The cellular node of communalism–the major form of freedom put forward by communalism–is the community assembly. Communal assemblies are needed for self-management to exist on the community scale. Communal assemblies are places for deliberation and collective decision making about political and economic actions. Community assemblies can have embedded participatory councils/committees/working groups/delegate roles to implement specific decisions within the bounds of the overall decision/policy/mandate/protocols decided by community assemblies. Community assemblies can co-federate to develop inter-communal mutual aid, coordination, decision making, economics, and actions where delegates are sent back and forth between co-federal councils and communal assemblies where policy making power stays at the lowest level in the hands of people directly. In additional to communal assemblies, communalists should favor an ecosystem of popular organizations and social movements that use liberatory means towards liberatory ends.

Constitutions/Points of Unity:

Directly democratic forms are needed for direct collective decision making about what people want to do and about what effects them. However, directly democratic forms can be instrumentalized towards anti-democratic, non-egalitarian, and otherwise unfree content. To avoid such authoritarian form and content, it is important that decisions people make in the assembly–and the assembly form itself– are in harmony with certain liberatory principles. Communalist assemblies have shared practices for political form and content at least include direct democracy, participatory relations, communal self-governance, non-hierarchy, and co-federalism. Such principles can exist as points of unity for shared practice within an organization; existing within the structure of communalist assemblies and existing within the constitutions, bylaws, bills of rights, and programs of a communalist assemblies.

Examples of communalist principles and practices are: Direct democracy, Non-Hierarchy, Co-federalism, Communal Self Governance, and Ecology. Direct democracy within free association of persons, without ruling classes, and without hierarchical relations, makes it so the form and content of assemblies are not towards hierarchical forms and arbitrarily limiting freedoms of persons. Co-federalism allows for interdependent cooperation with other communal assemblies and organizations. Communal self governance is needed for self governance on every scale and to prevent the privatization of politics over and above communities. Ecological praxis is an orientation towards solving ecological problems caused by social problems and using ecological technics. Those general principles that can be applied to particular contexts in a large variety of ways– and can exist within the structure as common practices, processes, and as rights an assembly is designed to uphold and protect. Ideally, some of the people helping to start a communalist assembly should be well versed in the basic theory of libertarian socialism, communalism, social ecology and/or other philosophies and practices based on things like “communal property”, usufruct, direct collective decision making.

Strategy:

The strategy of communalist assemblies is to build dual power against capitalism, statecraft, and hierarchy more broadly by using communalist means, structures, and processes to develop communalist ends. Communalism involves oppositional politics and direct action–opposing that which ought not exist and taking action without being mediated by hierarchy within one’s own organization. Another dimension of communalism is reconstructive politics and mutual aid–developing social freedom and meeting people’s needs through horizontalist organizations and actions that pool skills, tools, needs, abilities, resources on various scales and creating alternative institutions and infrastructure. Another important goal is popular education–internal and external to communal assemblies. It is important to create a form and content of communalism and that requires convincing people through reasoning of libertarian socialist practices–such as direct democracy and non-hierarchy. An important way to do so is to focus together on common needs and common struggles and to use argumentation for why horizontalist self-organization, mutual aid, and direct action etc. can help arrive at various goals people have better than other means (such as hierarchical ones) and why libertarian socialist methods (direct democracy, mutual aid, direct action, etc.) are more ethical and effective at arriving at various things that people value.

Communalist assemblies and embedded pariticipatory councils can develop oppositional and reconstructive politics at the points of extraction, production, distribution, reproduction, and community life. Community assemblies and embedded councils can develop, help with, and participate in many different kinds of oppositional and reconstructive politics. This includes everything from direct action such as occupations of hierarchical infrastructure, full on expropriation of land, means of production and fruits of labor, civil disobedience, rallies, strikes, blockades, boycotts, insurrections, marches, community self defense, to mutual aid such as things like free food distribution, free resource distribution, developing people powered infrastructure, etc.

The process of developing a libertatory ecosystem of collectives is done in part through developing embedded councils /working groups of community assemblies. However, it is also through incubating and/or assisting various groups–such as other communal assemblies, community and worker controlled cooperatives, solidarity networks, direct action collectives, mutual aid networks, community gardens, popular education organizations, free stores, tenants’ assemblies, radical unions, ecological technology projects, issue specific groups, and more. These building blocks can collaborate to help each other out mutualistically and create alternative and counter institutions to business as usual.

Communal assemblies–outside of developing their own projects– can coordinate with and incubate organizations rooted in direct democracy, direct action, and mutual aid. Together, such building blocks can join up to become more than the sum total of their parts in mutualistic relationships. Such a strategy can integrate more fragmented movements while uniting them on terms of unity that are in harmony with libertarian socialist practices. In a sense, communalism is to community organizing as anarcho-syndicalism is to workplace organizing.

As such building blocks of a potential dual power start developing, they can coordinate and form alliances and joint-projects and actions. As communal assemblies start developing across different blocks, neighborhoods, cities, and regions, they can form more formal co-federal structures of community assemblies on various scales. Such projects aim towards decentralizing power, meeting people’s needs, while building horizontalist governance structures to replace hierarchical governance structures, before, during, and after revolutionary moments.

The above approach is prefigurative in the sense that such communal assemblies and self-managed institutions try to model the world they want to create in their formal structures and processes, but it is also strategic in the sense that it realizes that the new world does not exist yet and is something that we need to build from the conditions that exist. The formal features of communalism are necessary but insufficient for communalist goals. Although it is of course true that instrumental strategic reasoning without due ethical considerations can lead to brutality, merely prefigurative approaches–especially ones that don’t realize a distance between means and ends, and not just where there should be consistency between them–can lead to toothless projects with no meaningful attempt to re-organize power and confront hierarchical conditions. Given the current conditions, questions like “how do we reach out beyond the current left and organize with the unorganized?”, “what collectives should we try to build?”, “what collectives already exist that we can work with on various levels?”,  “how do we spread popular education?”, “how do we keep our eyes on the prize while engaging in intermediate steps?”, “how do we link short term and long term goals?”, “which project should we focus on with our current levels and limits of capacity?” “how do we reach out without sacrificing what should be minimal principles?”, “how do we use our collective capacity in a way where we become more than the sum total of our parts?” etc. are just some of the many important questions one should be asking oneself and one’s comrades when organizing a communalist project.

ByLaws:

Bylaws should be fleshed out as a communalist assembly develops. A good initial aspect of the bylaws is some kind of decision making process. This can be as simple as follows:

  1. Decisions ought to be made through deliberation. Critiques, agreement, dissent, amendments, counter-proposals, etc. should be included as well as attempts to round out decisions through dialogue. The assembly tries to develop consensus. When there is not a consensus, then the decision is further deliberated upon and then gets put to vote.
  2. If consensus is not arrived, at then decisions ought to be made by simple majority–decentralizing decision making and veto power.
  3. Proposals and Decisions ought to be filtered through the constitutions/bylaws/bill of rights and/or points of unity for process. *and such constiutions/bylaws/bill of rights/ should be rooted in direct democracy/non-hierarchy/co-federation/etc.
  4. Committees, delegates, etc. must be administrative rather than make policy over and above the assembly. They are to self manage within the mandates from the general assembly.
  5. Committees and delegates are to be subject to immediate recall by the general assembly.

This can be fleshed out and adapted as needed. Focusing too much on bylaws at the beginning can turn people away and also become overly process oriented. However, not having a good process can lead to hierarchical and arbitrary power instead of a clear horizontalist democratic process. It is important to use a sufficiently ethical and practical process to develop actions and ends worth developing– rather than a reductive focus on process. Having some kind of liberatory structure from the beginning for people to agree to, tweak, adapt, can help set a project up on directly democratic terms. It is important to think about deliberation and decision making processes, transformative and restorative justice processes, various delegate positions, and ways that committees and affiliated organizations relate to the general assemblies etc. as these kinds of things will come up in the process of organizing.

The overall policy of a communalist project is decided by the general assembly and embedded committees then self manage the implementation of that policy within the boundaries set by the general assembly. Individual delegates would have no policy making power and would serve purely communicative, coordinative, and administrative roles within their mandate. Such roles should be rotated and there should be a fostering of general knowledge throughout the assembly project about how to do various roles. Part of the assembly project is a process of education for those involved to find out how to self manage an organization. People bring their different propositional and practical knowledge to the table and the assembly should serve as a teaching and learning experience for all involved as people work on shared projects.

Embedded Councils/Committees/Working Groups:

When there is a project voted on at an assembly, an embedded council/committee/working group can be started to then implement the project. The implementation of the project should be within the bounds of the policy made from below (by a community assembly or co-federation of assemblies). The committee–formed of volunteers who agree enough with the policy made from below (a policy that is at least in harmony with minimal libertarian socialist processes and practices)– then self manage the implementation of the policy and report back to the community assembly project that it is a part of. Committees can have broad or specific mandates–and depending on the specific decisions and contexts, the mandates should be more specific or more broad. For an example, a direct action or solidarity network committee of an assembly might be given the broad mandate of 1. Organizing according to applicable bylaws, bill of rights, points of unity 2. to take direct action against landlords and bosses 3. Towards mutual aid for tenants and workers and 4. as A direct action wing of a general assembly that can do (or agrees to do) X, Y, and Z actions/kinds of actions (otherwise further deliberation with assembly would be needed for a specific action or kind of action to be done by this committee of the assembly) 5. that Reports back to and is accountable to the assembly. Responsibilities from the assembly to the working group can be expressed as well which could look like 1. specific or general assistance from an assembly and other collectives within the assembly, 2. the assembly helping to promote and mobilize for specific direct actions during meetings 3. use of broader communications infrastructure of an assembly for promoting specific actions, etc. It will make sense to make some committees open to all members (or non members), and to make other committees closed (where only those delegated from the general assembly can join).

Sometimes it makes more sense for strategic reasons for some committees to eventually develop into relatively separate organizations. This can be a really positive thing for the working group project and the assembly project and even an initial intention of some working groups of assemblies (for example when an assembly has limited capacity and needs to focus on some projects and not others, when the working group makes more sense as its own membership organization, etc.). However, depending on the context, full separation from the assembly and other affiliated organizations can be an inhibiting factor for both the assembly and the other collectives because of benefits they can all gain from each other– including but not limited to mutual aid between groups, collaboration between groups on joint projects, developing an ecosystem of collectives that work together and are part of a greater project than any specific issue, etc. Instead, it can makes sense for some committees that no longer make sense as full on embedded councils of community assemblies to become affiliated autonomous organizations– working together with the assembly project in some kind of way when it makes sense for common goals. Whether a specific project should become embedded within assemblies, affiliated with assemblies, or separate from assemblies will vary from project to project and context to context. On one level ecosystems of liberatory organizations and movements are needed, but if different groups do not strategically combine forces to row in a similar enough and mutualistic direction, then movements can be limiting their potential and even acting in a way that is less than the sum total of their parts!

Under full communalism, politics and economics would be integrated into co-federated networks of horizontalist communes with embedded self managed councils for implementation of communal decisions. The embedded councils would be made out of volunteers who self manage within policy made by the community assembly or co-federation of community assemblies–assisted by liberatory technology. Auxiliary councils and groups–in harmony with libertarian socialist and communalist rights and responsibilities– would also exist. However, it is important that such auxiliary groups do not privatize the means of existence and production needed for reproduction of political economic life, horizontalism, and communal self management. Production would be for needs, desires, and use. And accordingly, distribution would be according to needs, desires and use where all would have access to a cornucopia that is reproduced and developed by participatory labor, work, and action assisted by ecological and liberatory technology– including the automation of toil and the elimination of roles that don’t serve a good social function (such as cops, bosses, salespeople, the entirety of the fossil fuel industry, etc.).

Delegate Roles:

Although communalism is against any kind of representative policy making, communalism is not against coordinative, communicative, and administrative roles. Such roles should be mandated and recallable and have no policy making power. Such roles should be rotated–so no one person has to do too much work and so everyone gets as much general knowledge as possible. Sometimes it can make sense for some roles sometimes to be done by co-delegates. Such roles can include things like a secretary or note taker position, a treasurer position, a digital outreach coordinator (emails, website, social media, etc), and co-federal delegates to coordinate between assemblies and then go back to the assembly base where actual decisions are made.

A crucial goal of delegates, outside of the functions they are delegated to do, is to organize themselves out of their positions and make sure the torches gets passed on– along with the knowledge needed for their roles. One way to do this is to stagger the role so the new person coming into a delegate role learns from the prior delegate. Delegates can exist through nomination and self nomination and then a vote (or lack of dissent). Some kind of spinning role chart (that passes applicable delegate roles in a circle overtime between all members of an organization) or sortition process might also make sense for some delegate roles in some assemblies. In the above processes people can opt out of specific delegate roles, but such processes can encourage shared labor, shared knowledge of how to do various delegate functions, and encourage people and assemblies to not turn such temporarily held roles into something permanently occupied by anyone. The more the social reproduction of an assembly is shared among many participants–within and outside of specific delegate roles– the more resilient that overall project will be (all else being equal).

Before one starts a Communalist Project:

Before a communal assembly project launches, it is ideal to have people who have some shared principles to do some preparation work together. It is good to have a core group of people who understand the basic strategy of communalism. It might make sense to even start as a reading group to review the basics of social ecology and to theorize what it would mean to apply communalist praxis to one’s specific location. It can be helpful if the people helping you start an assembly have various kinds of diversity within them and diverse and differentiated social relations for both ethical reasons of inclusion and strategic outreach.

Before one brings a communalist project to the public, it can make sense to have some kind of pre-drafted idea of the structure and orientation of the project–however skeletal it may be. This idea and project can then be proposed to and adapted by people who are interested in co-authoring a communalist project. Depending on the context one is in, one can adapt the bylaws, bill of rights, or points of unity for practice to be more and less fleshed out– fleshed out enough to be coherent but flexible enough to be adaptable and to include a large realm of permissibility within the bounds of essential communalist processes and practices. Although the following will have to be deliberated amongst people and adapted to needs and preferences of participants: having a consistent meeting space ready, a proposed structure (which may or may not include skeletal versions of bylaws, bill of rights, points of unity for practice, program, strategy, etc. to propose), an outreach plan, some initial projects that can be started, and adequate time to really think about how to launch the project can all be useful before starting a communal assembly.

It is important to find people already very sympathetic and then reach out to de-politicized or more moderately politicized people–that is to reach inwards for the express purpose of gaining capacity to reach outwards with such a specific project. However, communalist assemblies strive to be popular organizations rather than ideologically specific groups or “lower common denominator of the left” kinds of organizations. The goal is to reach outwards to people through an assembly project without compromising on what should be minimal practices of communalism.

An organization can only launch once– it is best to plan how it is strategically introduced to the public. However, the starting point is distinct from its overall developmental potential and is just one of many features to think about when developing a community assembly. It is almost always more sustainable long term for a group to start out moving at a slow pace–working on short term goals and tangible achievable projects through horizontalist processes– to build themselves up before they more fully reach out and take on more difficult projects. It is also possible to start a communalist project too slowly– to the point where important moments get missed where it would have made sense for a project to have already been introduced to the public and/or already tackling larger scale issues. No amount of prior planning will be able to exhaustively deal with the turbulence of putting theories into action, but thinking about how to develop a meaningful beginning and trajectory is far more fruitful than throwing darts at a board in the dark.

Sometimes it makes sense to start a community assembly– or movement assembly– around a specific issue or project that people are interested in. Other-times it makes sense to start assemblies to find out what issues or projects should be focused on. Both approaches have pros and cons. Single issue based projects can lead to getting pigeonholed into particular areas that are reductionist compared to the wide array of content assemblies can enact. Starting with assemblies to find issues to develop together can be too vague and abstract to motivate people at first. Overtime, both assemblies and specific projects that they focus on need to develop in tandem and the way a specific assembly starts is less important than how it develops.

Research/Community Mapping:

When starting such a project, one should look at potential comrades and people trying to stop a communal assembly project from happening. Look at the other building blocks of an ecology of movements in one’s own locale. It might be an IWW branch, a local libertarian socialist group, a direct action network, a mutual aid network, cooperatives, ecologically oriented groups, community spaces etc. Look at local problems and aspirations people have to see what projects make sense. Even though communalism ought to be a secular project including freedom of and from religion, reaching out to left leaning religious congregations–and members of other congregations– can be an important thing to do. Find out people and organizations that might be sympathetic so they can be invited to assemblies.

Research various “pressure points” of hierarchical systems in your area and various ways action can be applied by popular movements to achieve liberatory goals. Research far right organizations in your community. Be aware of who the local ruling class are. Research potential for police repression in your area and generally. Although there is general research one can do that will be relevant to organizing in a particular context, research and community mapping should be adapted to specific projects and goals and integrated as part of strategy in assemblies and embedded councils.

Outreach:

Outreach can be done in a plurality of ways. Word of mouth, face-to-face , and one-on-one interactions and communication are very important. One-on-one outreach can also be done via one on one text invitations. Door-to-door approaches are underused and very effective at reaching out beyond the already existing left. Flyering is important as well–whether or not one lives in a city that has a culture of flyering for events. Bus-stops, neighborhoods, cafes, walls for postering events throughout cities, etc. should be flyered as much as possible when trying to do outreach. Make sure that the flyers include relevant information about the organization, some explanation of what the event is, as well as the time and space location of the event, and where to find more information. Handbill flyers can be made to pass out to people at various political, countercultural, subculture, and common spaces, every day events, and while people run into people throughout their everyday travels. Handing out handbills and flyers to many people and/or creating flyering teams and work parties can help make the such processes enjoyable and shared. Announcing an event during announcement sections of groups that are fine with announcements for other groups can also be fruitful. Potlucks and Block parties can also be good ways to do outreach and build community as part of a community assembly project. Do not underestimate the potential of collective action projects to help build community for further actions. The internet is an important tool as well–but has many limits. Text message groups, social media events, and internet groups can be used to reach out to people and do in-reach–but they should never be relied upon at the expense of face to face organizing. Having an email list-serve is an important tool to utilize for in-reach. And of course outreach through direct action and shared participation in social struggles is also indispensable.

Many people are not initially radicalized (as in activated to get involved in transformative politics) by going to meetings, but by going to direct actions. Many people are initially radicalized by mutual aid projects instead of direct actions. Many people are initially radicalized through popular education rather than through any of the above, etc.  It is often when people deepen their understandings of activities within the processes of direct actions, mutual aid projects, and popular education that people often see the importance of going to meetings, making collective decisions, and doing the activities that make popular organizations, direct actions, and revolutions possible.

Initial projects one Can Start:

Exactly what projects to begin with can be tricky, and is not identical across different contexts. One way to start community assemblies and projects within assemblies is to host issue focused forums and assemblies where single issues are deliberated about in depth. Alternatively, people can start with an open assembly to find out what to focus on. One function communal assemblies are able to do particularly well is prefigure the commons (means of existence production held in common accessed freely according to needs) via communal self-management. However, to meaningfully develop the commons on a large enough scale, the means of existence and production must be seized from hierarchical rule. Mutual aid projects of some kind are often ideal projects to start. They are usually lower risk than oppositional political actions (not that “low risk” is the only thing to take into consideration). Mutual aid projects– the use of horizontalist organization to meet people’s needs via multi-directional support– lead towards mutual thriving of persons involved while disproportionately helping those in poverty and otherwise most in need. And mutual aid projects do the above while using a horizontalist forms, participatory organizing, with communistic content. Additionally, mutual aid projects are generally the most agreeable possible projects! Oppositional direct actions are usually more controversial and usually involve more risk. That being said, direct action arms of community assemblies are important to bridge abstract problems and solutions to concrete actions that can be done as well as give the assembly a class struggle and class abolitionist ethos. If assemblies lose an oppositional character entirely, then they can easily become pejoratively utopian. Direct action committees of assemblies and Solidarity Networks are ways that people can take action against the state, capitalists, bosses, and landlords in ways that use direct action towards meeting people’s needs. Sometimes because of various conditions (urgency, theoretical composition of people, strategic openings, for strategic reasons wanting the assembly to start with an explicit class struggle approach etc.) direct actions make the most sense as starting places for communalist assemblies to organize around. In other time space locations with different social relations, community gardens, community technology projects, community infrastructure development, and community-cooperative development might make more sense as the most initial projects to start. Fundraisers for political events, potlucks, and block parties can be ways to build community, have fun, and spread political messages through political causes, pamphlets, relationships, and dialogue (and are relatively easy to do). Skillshares, lectures, reading groups, and other popular education projects can help facilitate theoretical and practical knowledge and can serve as social gatherings for further organizing and can help people do better actions in the future through learning better theory and critical thinking skills. Despite mutual aid projects often making sense as the first projects community assemblies start, there are many good first projects communalist assemblies can start and no uniform formula for what problems should be tackled first and what projects should be started first.

One of the strengths of community assemblies is their potential to do a lot of different types and sub-types of activities. However, this can also be a strategic weakness of community assemblies if this is not utilized well; for if community assemblies are “biting off more than they can chew”, they can wind up squandering effort in many projects that do not have enough capacity. Inversely, “planting a plurality of seeds” can allow some to blossom. Finding ways to strategically row the communal ship together requires adjusting how many projects an assembly takes on overtime as well as which projects an assembly project takes on.

Where to start: Block by Block or more city wide organizing?:

One way to start communal assemblies is going block by block to organize specific blocks and neighborhoods into block assemblies and neighborhood assemblies. Another way to begin such a process might be to organize a broader city wide assembly project of some kind and then decentralize into neighborhood assemblies and block assemblies as people join and capacity allows–and as people find out which particular blocks they want to focus on. If one is starting with a block by block approach to organizing, then people should most fundamentally organize where they are and where they go. However, some neighborhoods and regions within a city that more fruitful for organizing and are important to focus on–due to both economic and theoretical compositions of various neighborhoods. Working class neighborhoods are the most important neighborhoods to organize–as well as neighborhoods that have good class consciousness and are more left leaning in general (and those initial groups can help the assembly model spread elsewhere). However people can and should start liberatory organizing wherever they are– and wherever they go. Common needs, common struggle, and common values are different bridges that can lead towards communalist practice.

There is an important urgency to change the world and therefore we must take our time with these projects and build them in a generative way. Do not expect the assembly project to be successful overnight. Although more periodic kinds of groups that only exist for a few months–and institutions that only last a few years–can do a lot of good actions within a city or area, organizations that continue onward many years beyond their initial jumping off point, that are ethically prefigured with a strategic content, can potentially arrive at long term sustained goals and even revolutionary goals.

General Principles and Particular Contexts:

Communalist assemblies can be started in a variety of ways. Different approaches of applying general principles make more and less sense in different contexts. The general principles of communalism are necessary but insufficient for their application to particular conditions. The cutting edge of communalist praxis deals with applying the general principles to particular contexts and creating strategic content with tactics appropriate for such strategy. This is where things get relatively tricky and where general theory and approaches fail to be a sufficient guiding path–as necessary, desirable, and important as they are. The ethics of communalism can adapt to various geological, ecological, preferential, social, political, economic, historical, cultural, and individual differentiations while still retaining its essential features. And the only way to make such a path is by organizing together with people using communalist processes to solve political economic and social problems and co-create collective decisions and actions.

Applying libertarian socialist communal assembly projects will look different in different places despite retaining general lower common denominators. Even though there might be surprising similarities about applying general principles to particular contexts, Applying such principles in Oakland will look different than applying such principles in New York City, which will look different than applying such principles in Jackson, Mississippi, which will look different than applying such principles in rural Vermont, which will look different than applying such principles in Kobane or Mexico City. Such locations are also not static communities; they are in process, so within a few years the best ways to apply such principles to particular locations might significantly change. Ways of applying general principles to particular contexts–and even the general principles themselves– are subject to change if there are sufficiently relevant variables that emerge. There are always ways to implement communalist projects in better ways– even compared to projects that are doing well.

Shared conditions vs. shared principles vs shared practice:

Not having sufficiently coherent form or content can create incoherence to the point where the assembly subverts its own liberatory features. A way to round out an assembly or a collective without making the group based on shared ideology is to have common practices rooted in libertarian socialist principles embedded in the structure, constitution, bylaws, bill of rights, and (as much as possible) culture of an assembly. Not everyone has to agree to libertarian socialism or communalism to agree with terms of practice that are in harmony with libertarian socialism or communalism. Such an approach has a lot of the benefits that a shared ideology approach has yet is nonetheless distinct and serves different functions.

One of the goals of a communalist project is to reach out to people who do not yet share communalist theory. Putting forward programs and points of unity that groups should be rooted in and bounded by, if not done well, and adapted to the specific kind of organization one is trying to build and context one is in, can unnecessarily inhibit reaching out to people who do not already agree. For example, imagine how unnecessarily alienating it might be to ordinary people to start a community assembly in the USA in 2019 that starts with a program calling for “full communism” with that exact wording. It would make more sense strategically, for the sake of communication, for the program to talk about giving everyone free necessities of life, developing a commons, mutual aid, self-managed economics etc. We need to find ways to communicate communalist principles and practices, have them enshrined within the structure and alive in the content of popular assemblies, without unnecessarily alienating people and without making communalist ideology (a specific kind of libertarian communism) a prerequisite for joining such assemblies (and without sacrificing the ethical and strategic substance of communalist practice at the same time).

There is no one size fits all approach to how people get involved in social movements and start participating with others. Common conditions, and/or desires and/or principles can develop into shared practices and organizations, and such a process can nourish shared principles, and from there those new shared principles can nourish future actions, etc. If sufficient common ideology exists between people, it is possible for specific kinds of shared ideology based organizing to happen (that can be done via ideologically specific libertarian communist groups distinct from popular organizations but with members who are participants in both). Such ideologically specific groups can create social movement groups and popular organizations. Additionally, members from ideologically specific groups can join social movement groups and popular organizations and advocate for direct democracy, direct action, mutual aid, etc. within social movement groups and popular organizations to help those already existing groups achieve their own goals. The libertarian socialist strategy of doing so has been called “organizational dualism”, and it aims towards the self management of popular organizations and social movements rather than a hierarchical vanguardist approach.

What might inhibit Communal Assemblies:

Inhibiting factors of communal assemblies will differ from region to region over time and space. Capitalism and the state are some of the greatest inhibiting factors, for they cause everything from a lack of public space to organize in, lack of access to the means of existence and production, to cops enforcing unjust laws, etc. Rightwing populists and reactionary formations inside and outside of the state will be particularly violent towards leftward tendencies. There is of course TINA–There is no Alternative– a prevailing theoretical and practical orientation that inhibits any radical critique of that which exists . Liberal cooptation is another thing to be wary of given that liberal ethos can take libertarian form and subsume it to liberal content (or form). The democratic party has a whole array of activists and movements that spread electoral reductionism that can try to take over and defang leftist organizations. Marxist-Leninist tendencies can try to restructure communal assemblies into hierarchical forms aimed towards state socialist revolution, whereas anti organizationalism will try to inhibit collective decision making processes and organizational structure altogether. Racism, sexism, Anti-Semitism, etc. are inhibiting factors that make it difficult to build relationships and trust to work together on common issues and issues that drastically affect some people more than others. Furthermore, such racist, sexist, and oppressive relations inhibit the kind of egalitarian relations needed for a project to be worth fighting for. Such issues exist both within the wider society and within left circles. Identity-reductionist attempts to deal with oppression lead to ways that are not holistic enough to build solidarity–and such approaches do not know how to deal with political economic structures that underpin structural forms of oppression.

Communal assemblies should embody general communalist principles and adapt to particular contexts they are in and surrounded by–not just either or. Furthermore, communal assemblies should be both prefigurative–in the sense of building and reproducing the kinds of structure that ought to exist in the new world–and strategic in the sense of being oriented towards certain principled goals and trying to achieve them rather than mere development of a good process/structure. The strategic aspects should be in harmony with good principles rather than at the expense of them.

Communal assemblies should also build relationships with people and not just be a political process. The development of a culture of care, mutualistic friendship, and trustbuilding are important steps to actual decision making processes and organizational resilience– and developing a good society! However, such assemblies should not devolve into a mere politics of friendship– people do not have to be close friends with one another to work meaningfully together politically on shared goals through shared processes.

Communal assemblies can also be inhibited by decisions made by communal assemblies themselves! This can happen through decisions that inhibit horizontalist form, lack of strategic content, lack of good relations between persons, lack of prudent vision (which CAN take the form of a focus on militancy at the expense of reaching out), not reaching out to people, not educating people, not having good enough structure, etc. No matter how good the form of an organization is, it does not necessarily entail good content. Even if good form and points of unity for practice are carried through within the content of an organization, the content itself might not be strategic and generative towards long term goals.

Is the Assembly the best place for you to start?:

Although communal assemblies are an important–in my opinion the most important– building block for revolution (that can also catalyze other building blocks), they are also not necessarily the best form for every particular group of people to start as the first project they do within every particular context they are in. It might make more sense to build other building blocks of a revolution first such as a solidarity network, a tenants’ union, a houseless solidarity organization, a mutual aid organization, a cooperative federation, a popular education group, an ideologically specific libertarian socialist group etc. It is easiest to start a communalist assembly when liberatory organizations and cultural dimensions already exist. However, communal assemblies can act as a catalyst for those very institutional and cultural shifts and can be a great project to start even when there is not already a broader left social movement ecosystem.

Learning from history:

Fortunately, when starting a community assembly–or some other kind of popular organization– we do not have to completely reinvent the wheel: Looking through history we find many ways different democratic and communal projects have made decisions together, have increased various social health criteria, happiness, and freedom, and various ways such projects have fallen short of their most liberatory goals. There are important lessons we can find throughout the history of human freedom. Looking to revolutions such as Rojava, The Zapatistas, anarcho-syndicalist Spain, Shinmin Korea, and the Free Territory are especially helpful. We can glean the various lower common denominators and particularities of each of the above movements and see what parts of the above revolutions make sense for us to apply in our specific contexts. The history of freedom is far more expansive than libertarian socialist revolutionary history: it includes thousands of egalitarian societies throughout history across many cultures, regions and continents. The history of freedom also includes issue specific social movements, the history of syndicalism, the broader history of anarchism, socialism, communism, the left, and far more. It would be foolish to not glean gems from revolutionary history. However, this can only be done well through critical investigation of history– including a critical evaluation of one’s favorite revolutions and societies in history. A good analysis of history would characteristically help with a good understanding of what the universalist principles and practices of communal and democratic relations are– as well as what the more contingent principles and practices of various communal and democratic relations are. A good analysis of history combined with good contemporary praxis will be able to remix the right principles and practices from history and adapt them to one’s specific context as new, unique, and uncharted relevant variables emerge. As we learn from history we must also remember that the answers to future problems have not been exhaustively answered by the past. Such an analysis would try to find anti-liberatory dimensions even in the most liberatory of organizations and movements–as well as strategic and tactical blunders made by various revolutionary groups. This would not be to do an unfair rejection of their most positive elements, but it would be to avoid the kind of non-critical cheerleading that inhibits us from seeing imperfections and ways specific and general projects can do better according to good ethical criteria.

A Critique of Jordan Peterson

Screen Shot 2018-11-15 at 3.46.20 AM

11/14/2018

Jordan Peterson ignores social causes of gender roles and relations and instead claims socially constructed gender roles and relations–politically, economically, and culturally– are immutable features of biology. Jordan Peterson also uses pseudoscience to claim that there is such a thing as biological races within human beings , and Jordan Peterson additionally claims that hierarchies are inevitable aspects of biological phenomena (hence his Lobster theory of hierarchy). Jordan Peterson’s atomistic analysis of the world–where society is reduced to mere individuals– leaves no room for the meaningful kind of collective change that we ought to have. People who want large scale qualitative social change get diagnosed by Jordan Peterson as people who are not accepting individual responsibility for their lives, and almost necessarily pushing for a world that is more chaotic than business as usual, and people who are trying to change aspects of society that are basically immutable and natural (upsetting the “natural order of things”).

Race, class and gender hierarchies are not equivalent throughout historical periods. In fact, they vary widely each of the above being historically constituted. For all of natural history up until humans, there are no institutional arrangements through which institutional hierarchies can form. For 95% of human history we have no evidence for institutionalized forms of command and obedience and ruling classes and ruling strata–that is no evidence of institutionalized hierarchies (Bookchin 2005). The first evidence of hierarchies takes us back several thousand years–patriarchy being one of the first hierarchies we have anthropological evidence for (Bookchin 2005). Patriarchy gendered relations to private/public spheres, command and obedience, relations to production, and social roles in general (Bookchin 2005). After the development of patriarchy, state structures start emerging–centralizing power via a political ruling class (Bookchin 2005). Capitalist class relations don’t develop until Agrarian England in the 1600’s as landlord-capitalist tenant-wage laborer relations develop in tandem with new commodification of land and labor, and commodity production for market to competitively accumulate value (Wood 2002) (Aston and Philpin 2005). Commercial networks were then inoculated, subsumed to, and expanded by this new capitalist class relationship which in turn subsumed other modes of production for competitive value accumulation (Wolf 2010). Notions of race along with race hierarchies are a relatively recent phenomenon developing with capitalism as specific forms of relations to production and roles, pseudo-speciation, and dehumanization.***

A list of evil ways of people can relate to one another without talking about good relations can overshadow other tendencies and potentialities of humans. There are wide arrays of ethically good kinds of human relations and behaviors including egalitarianism, mutualism, freedom, cooperative organization, solidarity, philia, imagination, creativity, and reasoning. Such capacities exist in spite of hierarchical relations which inhibit such capacities compared to good political, economic, and social relations.

Institutional hierarchies are not mere taxonomic hierarchies–such as family trees or ranking different kinds according to a particular metric. Institutional hierarchies are not equivalent to mere relative expertise compared to others in particular fields of propositional and practical knowledge. Institutional hierarchies are not mere real and perceived dominance patterns that exist in first nature. Institutional hierarchies are not reducible to, nor apparent in, non-institutional nature. The social definition of hierarchy is distinct from how the term is used by some (or even many) biologists. Jordan Peterson lumps and conflates all of the above together along with ruling classes and strata and then claims hierarchical relations are a necessary feature for human and non-human nature.

Not only does scientific and philosophical evidence show that institutional hierarchies are historically constituted, not innate to human biology, and highly mutable, there is also absurdly strong scientific evidence that hierarchies are consistently linked to negative social health effects. Class relations cause and are defined by structural violence–absolute deprivation of resources and relative deprivation of resources– which is the biggest cause we know of for negative social health including everything from violence rates, lack of childhood wellbeing, drug abuse, lack of education, to addiction rates more broadly (WIlkinson and Pickett 2018) (Mate 2018). Hierarchies are defined through limiting freedom according to centralized and arbitrary forms of rule as well as a competitive ethos shown to inhibit everything from collective and individual mastery of skills, mutual aid, as well as overall flourishing of persons (Kohn 2017) (Kohn 2018). Excess stress–in large part caused and exacerbated by hierarchical relations and a lack of good social relations– is related to almost every single disease (Sapolsky 2001).

Philosophical and scientific evidence points to institutional hierarchies as not being inevitable and institutional hierarchies being detrimental to human relations. Natural and social history point to plenty of alternatives to social hierarchies– as evident in 95% of human history as well as a history of freedom emerging in opposition to a history of hierarchy and domination (Bookchin 2005). This history of freedom is rich enough to contain periodic mutual aid and sustained mutual aid throughout history, direct action against authoritarianism throughout history, collective organizations and decision making in line with an ethics of freedom and egalitarianism, and a revolutionary history including everything from the Paris Commune, to The Free Territory, To Shinmin in Korea, to EZLN, to Rojava. Kropotkin’s analysis of mutual aid as a factor in evolution provides us with positive notions of human nature and potential (Kropotkin 2016). Although Kropotkin’s notion of mutual aid was at times overly romantic (by overly reducing human nature without hierarchy to mutual aid (Bookchin 1999)), it is something that can be built upon and refined. Even Darwin’s notion of evolutionary fitness was based on adaptability to environment rather than mere competition. Mutualism and indirect mutualistic relationships are well accepted among biologists and ecologists. However, mutual aid is not something that necessarily happens and thrives when hierarchical relations are not present among human populations.

We need good social relations–and not just the absence of evil social relations– to enable the flourishing of the human capacity for mutual aid and other virtues to filter our volition. And through institutions and culture, humans have the ability to alter the course of our own relations through deliberately restructuring our political, economic, and social relations. However, such capacity for volition is always entangled with and limited by conditions and is not free from causality and context. Yet nonetheless, higher order volition and deliberate reasoning exist on institutional, collective, and individual scales as caused causal factors of our own development and the development of the non-human world–without which we cannot explain day to day events and history. We ought not evade our social responsibility to restructure the world through appeals to pseudoscientific and conservative notions of human nature that claim that there is no alternative to business as usual.

///

***Ethnic discrimination–which exists prior to racism– is not equivalent to racialized forms of discrimination. Notions of race have no biological underpinnings–different shades of pigmentation do not constitute biological race categories. There are of course many other hierarchical structures, forms of oppression, and forms of arbitrarily limiting freedoms of persons than race, class, and gender hierarchies: such as religious hierarchies, ableism, nationalism and the nation state in particular, to unjust rules, to gerontocracy (arguably the first hierarchy), to heterosexism, to transphobia, to anti-Semitism, etc. Merely listing off such hierarchies, forms of oppression, and forms of arbitrarily limiting of freedoms of persons– and even defining them and briefly talking about them historically– does not do justice to the particularities of all of the above and the relations of all of the above to all of the above.

Hierarchical relations do not exist in reduction of each other, but affect one another and can underpin, catalyze, and even compete with other hierarchical relations. Here is a brief but by no means anywhere near exhaustive exploration into relations of hierarchies to hierarchies: Class relations underpin structural forms of racism along with racialized relations to production–although racism cannot be reduced to its structural forms. Similarly, class relations underpin the productive/reproductive split and patriarchal political and economic hierarchies–although gendered hierarchies are not merely reducible to such relations to production. Racism and patriarchy both have attitudinal, behavioral, ideological, and structural forms. Non-structural dimensions of racism and patriarchy can still exist after abolishing their structural forms–even though such political/economic forms are the most brutal forms of racism and sexism and the biggest perpetuators of racism and sexism broadly. As Bookchin said, “Without changing the most molecular relationships in society — notably, those between men and women, adults and children, whites and other ethnic groups, heterosexuals and gays (the list, in fact, is considerable) — society will be riddled by domination even in a socialistic ‘classless’ and ‘non-exploitative’ form. It would be infused by hierarchy even as it celebrated the dubious virtues of ‘people’s democracies,’ ’socialism’ and the ‘public ownership’ of ‘natural resources,’ And as long as hierarchy persists, as long as domination organises humanity around a system of elites, the project of dominating nature will continue to exist and inevitably lead our planet to ecological extinction,” (Bookchin 1980). Racism and patriarchy inhibit relationship building among the dispossessed, the working class, and non-ruling class broadly, which allows capitalism, statecraft, and arbitrary limits to freedom–which are problems in and of themselves– that underpin structural racism and patriarchy to continue with less opposition. There are a large variety of evil social relations that are neither eternal nor immutable aspects of human nature, but are instead historically specific and mutable social relations. A comprehensive understanding of them, their histories, their potentialities, and relations to other social phenomena requires a large scale investigation beyond the scope and scale of this particular essay.

“We live in capitalism. Its power seems inescapable. So did the divine right of kings. Any human power can be resisted and changed by human beings.” – Ursula K. Leguin

///

  1. Bookchin, Murray. The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of Hierarchy. Oakland, CA: AK Press, 2005.
  2. Aston, T. H., and C. H. E. Philpin. The Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-industrial Europe. Place of Publication Not Identified: Foundation Books, 2005.
  3. Wood, Ellen Meiksins. The Origins of Capitalism: A Longer View. Verso, 2002.
  4. Wolf, Eric Robert, and Thomas Hylland. Eriksen. Europe and the People without History. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2010.
  5. Wilkinson, Richard G., and Kate Pickett. The Spirit Level: Why Equality Is Better for Everyone. London: Bloomsburry Publ., 2014.
  6. Kropotkin, Petr Alekseevich. Mutual Aid: A Factor in Evolution. Charlestown, SC.: Createspace, 2016.
  7. Kohn, Alfie. No Contest: The Case against Competition. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2017.
  8. Kohn, Alfie. Punished by Rewards. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Trade & Reference Publishers, 2018.
  9. Maté, Gabor. In the Realm of Hungry Ghosts: Close Encounters with Addiction. Toronto: Vintage Canada, 2018.
  10. Sapolsky, Robert M. Why Zebras Dont Get Ulcers: An Updated Guide to Stress, Stress-related Diseases, and Coping. New York: W.H. Freeman, 2001.
  11. Bookchin, Murray. Anarchism, Marxism and the Future of the Left: Interviews and Essays, 1993-1998. Edinburgh: A.K. Press, 1999.
  12. Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018.
  13. Bookchin, Murray. Toward an Ecological Society. Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1980.

An introduction to Utopian Thinking

 

08/17/18

Utopia is defined as either a good place or no place. In some sense the different definitions can be reconcilable because as people move towards the shores of utopia, the island itself drifts away. Such a metaphor describes that a perfectly good place is something that we never perfectly reach, and as we get closer there are new issues that arise that can get resolved in ways that make social relations even more utopian. However, just because we never arrive at perfection does not mean that people can not make progress towards utopia. Notions of good politics, economics, and social relations–good as in that which should be– should not be static ahistorical notions. Instead, notions of the good place ought to be rooted in actual possibilities–possibilities that are changing with conditions that are in a process of becoming.

 

Out of a critique of that which exists–the notion that the world is not perfect– comes a notion that the world could be better. From critique of that which exists, and knowledge of that which could be, a notion of that which should exist emerges out of actual possibilities–possibilities which are not all equivalent. However, the criteria for evaluating different possibilities is highly contested terrain. Different utopian theories try to answer the question of “what political, economic, and social relations ought to exist?”. Different utopian theories answer that question in a way that is more holistic than many normative ethical approaches because of the way that utopian theories flesh out criteria for a good society that often has multiple aspects not reducible to a singular particularistic metric.

 

Utopias describe and prescribe a gestalt of good principles and practices for political economic social relations rather than being preoccupied with the scale of what a good individual life is, or what good intentions are, or good particular actions, or good character traits. Those latter dimensions of the good that can only be answered holistically through a political, economic, and social context. Utopian theories are able to flesh out prescribed social relations that can either directly or indirectly arrive at the above normative ethical pursuits– or at least be a constitutive of or catalyzing towards  such normative ethical processes. Many utopian theories are even structured around arriving at classic normative goals such as consequentialism, virtue ethics, deontology, etc., whereas other utopian theories are related to classical normative ethical theories in indirect ways, or through seeing all of the above–theories of good place and more individuated theories of the good life– as mutually constitutive of each other in some way or another.

 

There are fictional utopias which  give a fictional account of what a good place would be like. Fictional accounts of the good place are connected to imagination–a key tool for finding out what could be. Fictional accounts of the good place are often rooted in philosophical utopian theories. It makes sense that utopian theories have a relationship to fiction because utopian processes are in many regards about co-creating a reality that doesn’t exist yet within the bounds of actual possibilities within the bounds of developmental conditions that exist. Philosophical utopias are broad theories of what good places ought to be. Theories of good political, economic, and social relations use some criteria of what the good is–whether it is explicit or implicit. People’s utopias are attempts to put philosophical utopias into practice–that is to apply general principles rooted in actual possibilities to concrete conditions. The theory and practice of utopia ought to mutually inform one another.

 

Pejoratively, utopia can mean something that is fantastical and not rooted in actual conditions. This can be seen in Marx’s critique of the utopian socialists. The pejoratively utopian socialists advocate for building utopia without a revolution that qualitatively shifts social relations. Marx critiqued the pejoratively utopian socialists for prescribing utopia within bourgeoisie property relations instead of through revolution. Such pejorative utopians advocate for merely building communes and cooperatives rather than building utopia out of oppositional politics. Such pejorative utopians are merely utopian rather than also looking at how a utopian process could unfold given the mode of production that exists. In many ways, Marx himself is deeply utopian. Marx acknowledges the importance of gleaning a vision of a good society from utopian thinkers–as Marx himself did. Marx’s notion of distribution according to abilities and needs and abolishing value–not just class relations– places Marx’s communism as more utopian than mere prescriptions of communes and cooperatives. Marx’s critique of pejorative utopianism is that the utopians do not root their analyses in the actual conditions developing–which under capitalism requires people to build utopia out of struggle to arrive at the good place. Marx’s critique of pejorative utopianism is not a critique of all forms of utopian thinking; in many ways Marx affirms and refines utopian praxis by adding the necessity of oppositional politics and changing the political economic limits of society as a whole–and not just building the new world without regard for the old.

 

However, it can also be said that Marx wasn’t utopian enough. Marx did not actually write much about what socialism and communism entails and ought to look like. Marx wrote far more critiquing capitalism than espousing communism. Marx was rather skeptical about our ability to flesh out utopian ideals beyond very minimal aspects. Although blueprint models of utopia are too strict, it can also be said that loose conceptions of utopia are too vague. The notions we have of the relations that ought to exist create a directionality for our praxis and require means that are constitutive of such ends if there are means constitutive of such ends. We ought to prefigure the new world within the shell of the old–which means we should flesh out what that new world ought to be to a significant degree– but we ought to take into consideration how the development of a new world is limited by the old world that still exists, as well as in part determined by practices employed to abolish the old world, and how the new world requires oppositional politics and revolution against the capitalist mode of production and hierarchical relations more broadly.

 

///

 

Endnotes:

 

  1. Anthropology of Utopia by Dan Chodorkoff
  2. The Communist Manifesto by Karl Marx

Notes on Generality and Particularity in Libertarian Socialist Praxis

The most incomplete part of libertarian socialist/communist/communalist praxis is less the general principles, practices and universals and more the particular application thereof to particular contexts. The general principles behind such a praxis are guiding factors that are necessary for good developmental praxis–given the relevant variables that exist– but are insufficient for telling us exactly how to apply them to particular time/space locations with changing conditions.

There are of course general principles for applying general principles to particular contexts, but even those general principles for applying general principles need further coherence, are developmental, need further illumination, and are themselves full of exceptions. The particular ways to apply libertarian socialist/communist/communalist praxis to your particular city will probably look at least a little different in 2010 then it will in 2018, and look different across cities within and between states. Different social movement compositions–including alternative institutions, class compositions, ideological/theoretical/cultural compositions etc. will affect what good overall strategy is in a particular location in some way or another.

Sufficiently relevant variables that change how to apply general principles to particular contexts are not equivalent to sufficiently relevant variables that change the general principles altogether. The point of a libertarian socialist/communist/communalist praxis was never to be a perfect blueprint, but to create a general praxis that can be applied to different contexts in different ways while maintaining the necessary features of the general praxis as the praxis adapts to relevant variables and develops overtime in progressive ways.

Formal and Informal Organization: Both and, or either or?

Screen Shot 2018-07-29 at 12.34.59 AM.png

 

When it comes to an ecology of movements, strategies, and tactics, and evaluating different approaches within anarchism and libertarian socialism, it possible to advocate for a plurality of different approaches in a coherent way. Being in favor of a plurality of different approaches and organizations–along with diversity of tactics more broadly– does not merely mean any movement, form, strategy, or tactic makes sense in any context. Ideally such an approach  seeks to form a coherent gestalt between different approaches. Communal assemblies, Radical Unionism, Periodic Direct Action, Direct Action Networks, Affinity Groups, Mutual Aid Networks, Cooperative Infrastructure, Popular Education, Anti-Fascism, Community Ecological Technology projects, etc. are all crucial to a revolutionary movement. Such practices fill different niches, and different people like different forms, strategies, and tactics more and less than others ones. Different people will have different skill-sets and different people find different forms, strategies, and tactics more principled/effective/enjoyable than other forms, strategies, and tactics in different contexts (making them more likely to participate in them). Making the argument for an ecology of forms, strategies, and tactics does not mean all ways of approaching all of the above are equivalent (in an extremely strange turn, some anarchists have argued against a “hierarchy of forms/strategies/tactics” which misunderstands both hierarchy and forms/strategies/tactics people can use to arrive at specific or general goals). Various forms and strategies can be described as keystone forms and strategies that disproportionately catalyze other forms, strategies, and tactics, and enable different niches of revolutionary action to be better filled.

Within anarchism there are many internal disagreements–although a signifcant amount of general agreement as well. One of the big distinctions within anarchism is organizationalism vs anti organizationalism. Sometimes this distinction is framed as mass anarchism vs. insurrectionary anarchism, or social anarchism vs lifestyle anarchism. Neo-anti organizationalism in the USA is often against formal organizations not just as a means towards anarchy, but disagree with formal organizations as parts of the ends of anarchy. In some places, anarchist unity has far less tension because organizationalist libertarian socialist tendencies are basically all that exists. In some contexts, anarchism as a movement is so coherent that the issues that will be discussed here will not apply.  However anti organizational anarchism did not originate in the USA and the USA does not have a monopoly on it. Arguably, a hard-line stance against formal organization of any kind– that goes beyond mere anti organizationalist means towards socialist ends– is incompatible with the classical anarchist movement. Whether that is the case or not based on how we are analytically or historically looking at anarchism is besides the point. In some places, especially the USA, anti organizationalist anarchists are considered part of the broad anarchist movement (sometimes to significant degrees), and sometimes such anti-organizationalists are against formally organized ends as well-.

Rather than organizationalists being against periodic direct action crews for not being organized enough, or periodic direct action crews being against formal organizing for not being immediately insurrectionary enough, we would be more ethical and effective if we were to acknowledge the insufficiency of various forms, strategies, and tactics we like more–or think are more ethical/strategic– and the necessity or desirability of some other ones. It seems to many that distinctions between formalist libertarian socialist means and informalist action are important and that such formal and informal means are compatible. This can lead many people to call for some kind of “anarchist unity” where different forms and strategies work synergistically together in some way or another.

 

Vague anarchist unity can appear to be a kind of “both and” approach that unites organizationalists and non-organizationalists in a kind of broader movement. In practice, such vague anarchist unity–and associations in accord with such principles– is often an “either-or” between organizing formally and organizing informally rather than a catalyst of both. And the way that the “either-or” plays out is often a reduction to informality and periodicity precisely because such aspects existing in some way or another are relatively uncontroversial between anti-authoritarians (unlike organizational approaches of which are not a lower common denominator between organizationalists and anti-organizationalists). This is because vague anarchist unity reduces unity to lower common denominators between differences in organizational and non-organizational anarchism rather than being a world where many worlds fit.

 

Given the fact that organizationalists are often–if not categorically– in favor of various kinds of informal and periodic actions, but that anti-organizationalists are against–not just not in favor of– organizational forms of anarchism, the lower common denominator between the two tends towards non-organizational approaches. It is ironically more specific or hyphenated forms of organizationalist anarchism–or libertarian socialism more specifically– that are able to develop a world where organizational and non-organizational worlds fit, whereas vague anarchist unity between organizationists and anti-organizationalists excludes organizationalist dimensions of action in its terms of unity while including anti-organizationalist approaches. By trying to maximally reach out to as many anarchists as possible through lower common denominator unity,  some actions needed for revolution (organizational ones) are excluded from practice. More specific kinds of libertarian communism (such as communalism and especifism for example) can arrive at coherence and general popularity in a far easier way than a vague anarchism that is defanged of its organizationalist and socialist dimensions.

 

Within libertarian socialism, there is general agreement that however important informal and periodic forms, strategies, and tactics are, that we need to build horizontalist institutional power to combat hierarchical relations, meet people’s needs, and build the new world in the shell of the old. There is also general agreement that strategies and tactics–including but by no means limited to informal and insurrectionary strategies and tactics– need to be evaluated within the context of generating libertarian socialist means and ends (because of the way that libertarian socialism is constitutive of the good). It is in these discussions–about when it makes sense to go on the attack for example– that libertarian socialism and informal anarchism can have incompatible goals and ways of evaluating forms, strategies, and tactics. Informalist anarchists and libertarian socialists will sometimes agree on forms, strategies, tactics, and goals, but nonetheless there are important different criteria these different theories have for the evaluation of actions and different goals overall– such as whether organization should even exist as a means and ends of a good society. Even though libertarian socialism is able to provide a kind of “both-and” approach when it comes to formal organizing vs. informalism, it does have different criteria for evaluating informal actions than anti-organizationalism, is in favor of organizational forms, strategies and goals, as well as an affirmation of society itself–which has somehow become a divisive notion in some anarchist circles.